Part Three: The Case Against Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research

Subscriber Only
Sign in or Subscribe Now for audio version

While there is currently widespread agreement that cloning-to-produce-children would be unethical, and even fairly broad support for its prohibition, public opinion is much more divided on the moral acceptability of cloning-for-biomedical-research.[1] This fact is partly attributable to confusion and partly to the different moral arguments that apply to the different ends cloning may serve.

Disputes over terminology surely compound the confusion. Some of the laws proposed to prohibit cloning-to-produce-children while permitting cloning-for-biomedical-research identify the act of “cloning” not with the creation of a cloned human embryo for research purposes, but only with the transfer of such an embryo to the uterus of a woman.[2] By contrast, many scientists, ethicists, and advocates use the term “cloning” for both practices — calling one “therapeutic cloning” and the other “reproductive cloning.” Though both these terms use the word “cloning,” they are still not entirely accurate. So-called “therapeutic cloning” will not be therapeutic for any patients in the near future, and will never be therapeutic for the cloned embryo, which will be destroyed. Furthermore, the distinction between the two implies that “therapeutic” cloning is not “reproductive,” when both are in fact forms of reproduction — both create new human life.

Unlike cloning-to-produce-children, which would be pursued only by those with a distorted understanding of the goods of procreation and family, cloning-for-biomedical-research serves a noble aim — the discovery of new knowledge that might make possible new modes of healing. But, like cloning-to-produce-children, and arguably to an even greater extent, cloning-for-biomedical-research involves immoral actions. In cloning-to-produce-children, after the embryo is cloned, it is transferred to a woman’s uterus so that it can develop into a child and be born, while in cloning-for-biomedical-research, the embryo is destroyed.

The availability of morally acceptable alternatives makes cloning-for-biomedical-research less justifiable. In the following pages, we show what is at stake in the debate over cloning-for-biomedical-research, and why it is important to reject human cloning whatever its purpose is.

Exploitation of Embryos

The central moral objection to cloning-for-biomedical-research is that it involves the deliberate killing of human embryos. Much of the debate over cloning-for-biomedical-research therefore concerns the question of the moral status of the embryo. Is the embryo “one of us,” despite its apparent lack of distinctively human features and capacities? Do these youngest of human beings deserve our care and protection, or are there purposes that are sufficiently important to warrant killing them or using them in experiments?

We maintain that, because human embryos are human beings, they must “never be used as a mere means for the benefit of others.”[3] Human embryos are members of the human species at the earliest stage of biological development. They are tiny in size and unfamiliar in appearance, but they are unmistakably individual human organisms — they do not become human at some later developmental stage. Occasionally scientists will aver that “science does not offer a hard-and-fast answer to the question of when human life begins.”[4] The notion that it is impossible for science to answer the question of when human life begins, or even that the question is meaningless, can be convenient for scientists who want to use embryos as raw materials in their technological projects, but it also represents an abdication of the responsibility of science to provide us not only with technological power over nature but also with answers to questions about nature, including answers that might make us reconsider the moral implications of some of our growing technological power over nature.

Cloning is not the only area of research that involves the deliberate destruction of human embryos. Most other forms of embryo-destroying research rely on embryos originally created for reproductive purposes left unused, stored frozen in IVF clinics.[5] But in the case of cloning-for-biomedical-research, human embryos are created for a purpose that requires their destruction. While the abandonment of one’s embryonic offspring represents one of the most morally vexing aspects of modern reproductive technologies, the creation of new human lives solely to produce biomedical research materials is a further, distinctive form of human exploitation.

Cloning-for-biomedical-research is a deeper violation of the meaning of the procreative act and the obligations we owe to future generations than cloning-to-produce-children. Both involve seeing offspring as products of our will, made to serve our purposes. But the direct aim of creating human lives in cloning-for-biomedical-research is the destruction of those lives, and the transformation of their bodies into biomedical research supplies. It literally involves manufacturing and commodifying human life: biotech companies advertise human embryonic stem cells as having been “derived under current Good Manufacturing Practice (cGMP) conditions.”[6] Advocates of such embryo-destroying research speak not of “embryos” but of the “products” of techniques like IVF or cloning.[7] In cloning-for-biomedical-research, the act of human reproduction is transformed entirely into a means of satisfying the desires and furthering the projects of autonomous adults, in complete indifference to the interests of the new human beings created.

As we will argue below, there are other serious moral problems associated with cloning-for-biomedical-research, including the exploitation of women who will be needed to provide eggs. And cloning-for-biomedical-research will lay the technical and practical groundwork for cloning-to-produce-children and a number of other morally troubling acts. But we should not forget that cloning-for-biomedical-research is already at the bottom of the slippery slope — it is an act of deliberately creating human beings solely so that they can be destroyed for the benefit of others.

Ethics of Egg Procurement

Procuring human egg cells for cloning research is both practically complicated and ethically problematic. Unlike some forms of human embryo research that can use embryos donated by fertility patients, cloning-for-biomedical-research involves the manufacture of embryos, which requires collecting oocytes from women — a process with significant medical risks to women that inherently exploits and commodifies women’s bodies.

Collecting eggs from women requires stimulating their ovaries to release more than one egg cell during ovulation. Women are prescribed a regimen of hormones that induce superovulation.[8] This procedure can result in a condition called ovarian hyperstimulation syndrome; researchers estimate that 3 to 10 percent of the egg-retrieval procedures performed in IVF clinics result in moderate or severe forms of the syndrome.[9] Severe cases can result in nausea; ovarian cysts; the enlargement of ovaries; changes in the viscosity, volume, or coagulation rate of blood; thromboembolism;[10] and even death.[11] The surgical procedure used to extract eggs also poses risks of pelvic infections and injuries, and internal bleeding.[12] Women providing eggs for research may be at lower risk for some of these complications than women undergoing fertility treatment,[13] but they are also undertaking these risks not as part of a course of treatment but for the sake of scientific research.

Obtaining human egg cells is an obstacle for cloning researchers, since it is not easy to find women willing to undergo the risk-laden and onerous procedures necessary to provide eggs. Whether or not scientists should be permitted to pay women for their eggs is one of the more hotly disputed policy questions concerning cloning-for-biomedical-research, since such payments may provide an inducement for women, especially poor women, to take on medically unnecessary risks. For that reason, some jurisdictions and institutions have placed limits on whether or how much scientists can pay women to provide eggs. While there are no federal laws in the United States restricting payments for egg donors (beyond limits on when and how federal dollars can be spent), some states have laws prohibiting payments for anything beyond reimbursement for direct expenses.[14] The National Academy of Sciences guidelines for stem cell research also endorse compensating women “only for direct expenses incurred as a result of the [egg-procurement] procedure,”[15] though these guidelines are not binding.

Guidelines from other professional associations, however, have been more permissive. The American Society for Reproductive Medicine guidelines allow that egg providers may be paid as much as $10,000 to “reflect the time, inconvenience, and physical and emotional demands associated with the oocyte donation process,” whether the women are providing eggs for fertility treatments or research.[16] The International Society for Stem Cell Research guidelines suggest that the research-oversight bodies at each institution decide for themselves whether to permit compensation,[17] on the grounds that such groups are able “to distinguish undue inducements from payments that appropriately acknowledge the interests of the subject.”[18] (For a brief survey of the policy debates over egg donation, see “Regulation of Egg Collection” in Part Four of this report.)

Some scientists and bioethicists who endorse cloning-for-biomedical-research have sought to loosen or eliminate restrictions on payments to women for eggs. Many human research subjects are compensated for their participation, and many women who provide eggs for fertility treatments are also paid for their eggs. So, the argument goes, for the sake of consistency women providing eggs for research should also be paid.[19] But the fact that human egg cells have been commodified in one instance does not justify their further commodification in other instances.

Advocates of cloning-for-biomedical-research also argue that payments do not represent “undue inducement” for women to undergo egg-collection procedures.[20] But it is somewhat disingenuous to downplay the incentive effect of payments, since the presence of payments clearly makes a difference in the decisions women make about whether or not to provide eggs: researchers report that it is difficult to find women willing to provide eggs if they will not be compensated, and women cite the absence of compensation as a chief reason for their decision not to undergo egg-collection procedures.[21] A survey of 230 women enrolled in a Columbia University program that paid them each $8,000 for their eggs found that just 2 percent of the women said they would have been willing to provide eggs without getting paid.[22]

Ethicists who endorse payment for eggs argue that following procedures for informed consent and limiting the amount of money paid for eggs can allow scientists to avoid exploiting women.[23] But as bioethicists Françoise Baylis and Carolyn McLeod argue in a critique of payment-for-eggs schemes, in practice it is impossible to eliminate exploitation, especially of the poor.[24] “There simply is no way to ensure, and no reason to expect, equitable participation in egg selling by rich and poor women,” they write.[25] Doing so would require researchers or review boards to track the economic situations of all egg sellers and ensure an impartial distribution, because simply showing that recruitment methods do not intentionally target poor women would not be enough to prevent the exploitation of the economically vulnerable.[26] The fact that a woman may freely consent to egg retrieval in full knowledge of its risks does not prevent undue inducement and exploitation, because the woman would most likely not have chosen to take on such risks had she been more financially secure. Exploitation of women providing eggs for fertility treatments is already too common, and more extensive commodification of eggs for research will only aggravate this problem.[27]

It is also necessary to respond to the claim that women are not being paid for their eggs but rather are being compensated for the risks and stress they undergo. For example, the American Society for Reproductive Medicine recommends that

Compensation based on a reasonable assessment of the time, inconvenience, and discomfort associated with oocyte retrieval can and should be distinguished from payment for the oocytes themselves. Payment based on such an assessment is also consistent with employment and other situations in which individuals are compensated for activities demanding time, stress, physical effort, and risk.[28]

But this argument, that it is the time and effort and not the eggs themselves that are being compensated for, is just a bit of rhetorical drapery obscuring the real purpose of the financial payments: securing more eggs. What researchers want is not the active participation of women in a shared research enterprise, but to extract valuable resources from women’s bodies — the raw materials for a biotechnological manufacturing process.

Future Prospects

Cloning-for-biomedical-research is itself a grave moral evil, but if it is actively pursued it will also make possible a host of other evils.

Most obviously, cloning-for-biomedical-research will lay the foundations for cloning-to-produce-children. The process of creating cloned embryos is the most technically challenging part of cloning-for-biomedical-research and also of cloning-to-produce-children. The act of transferring a cloned embryo to a woman’s uterus so that it can grow to term is likely to be little different from the act of transferring any embryo produced through IVF (although as of now, because of embryonic defects associated with cloning, cloned human embryos transferred to a uterus may not be able to survive to term[29]). So progress in the practice of cloning-for-biomedical-research necessarily contributes to expertise in cloning-to-produce-children. Furthermore, were cloning-for-biomedical-research allowed to progress, prohibitions on cloning-to-produce-children would become increasingly difficult to justify. It is safe to assume that some individuals and scientific organizations that support the prohibition of cloning-to-produce-children do so today in order to allay public concerns about cloning in general; their motivation to support such a ban would subside as cloning-for-biomedical-research advances and becomes entrenched. At the same time, it is difficult to imagine that, in a world in which cloned human embryos were being created for research in ever-growing numbers, no one would begin to implant them in wombs to bring babies to term. Indeed, were cloned embryos to become a commonplace part of biomedical research, not only would it be practically difficult to enforce laws or regulations prohibiting their transferal to wombs, especially in the largely unregulated U.S. assisted reproduction industry, but such laws or regulations would be morally odious, since they would consign all cloned human beings to death. (The immorality of these “clone-and-kill” laws is discussed further in Part Four.)

If research on human cloning were to become more acceptable to Americans and more engrained in the careers and projects of the scientific community, other biotechnological developments, as we shall see, may come to be regarded as permissible, desirable, or even necessary. The existence and acceptance of scientific techniques influences moral sensibilities about future techniques, and is often used as justification for setting aside moral objections. (For example, as mentioned above, many ethicists who advocate paying women for eggs point to the precedent of buying and selling eggs for fertility treatments as a justification for the further commodification of eggs for research.)

While it is worth exercising caution in appealing to the distant consequences of cloning research, the stakes in bioethical debates of this kind are high enough to justify taking seriously even some speculative worries. As the philosopher Hans Jonas argued in an essay on the implications of biological engineering:

Since no less than the very nature and image of man are at issue, prudence becomes itself our first ethical duty, and hypothetical reasoning our first responsibility. To consider the consequences before taking action is no more than common prudence. In this case, wisdom bids us to go further and to examine the use of powers even before they are quite ready for use. One conceivable outcome of such an examination could be the counsel not to let those powers get ready in the first place, i.e., to stop certain lines of inquiry leading to them, considering the extreme seducibility of man by whatever power he has.[30]

In the subsections that follow, we examine several morally troubling scientific and technological possibilities that may follow on cloning-for-biomedical-research and prove too seductive for humankind to resist.

Creeping extensions of embryo research. One of the medical possibilities most commonly cited as a rationale for pursuing cloning-for-biomedical-research is the prospect of using cloning as a large-scale source of patient-specific embryonic stem cells for cell-replacement therapies. The use of cloned human embryos for biological spare parts might become as regular a part of medicine as bone marrow transplantation is today. Even if some versions of such a future — like the possibility of “personalized biological repair kits” for every American[31] — seem exaggerated, that such a hypothetical is proposed at all by advocates is telling.

However, embryonic stem cells, taken from very young human embryos, are not the only possible medical applications of human cloning research. Scientists could grow cloned embryos in laboratories for longer periods in order to perform experiments on embryonic and fetal development, or to aid in the creation of technologies for growing fetuses outside the womb, or to develop organ primordia for transplantation.

Since the early days of the embryo debates, there has been a broad consensus among researchers and ethicists that embryos should not be experimented upon more than fourteen days after fertilization (discounting days spent frozen in storage). Countries that have used the fourteen-day limit in their laws and regulations governing research on human embryos include Australia,[32] Canada,[33] India,[34] Japan,[35] and the United Kingdom.[36] While the United States has no national laws prohibiting research on human embryos beyond fourteen days, professional societies[37] and the National Academies of Sciences[38] have adopted the fourteen-day limit as a guideline. (California’s state stem cell research agency uses a twelve-day limit for its funding decisions, on the same principle as the fourteen-day limit.[39])

The basis for this fourteen-day limit is that this is roughly when gastrulation occurs, a process after which the cells of the embryo lose their pluripotency, making it no longer possible for the embryo to split into identical twins. According to an influential 1984 British government report on human fertilization and embryology, the formation of the primitive streak in the embryo, a sign that gastrulation has taken place, “marks the beginning of individual development of the embryo.”[40]

The widespread adoption of this standard is somewhat surprising, considering its flimsy moral and scientific basis. Embryos are individual human beings from fertilization on — they do not acquire individuality with the emergence of new cell types or the first visible signs of a vertebrate body plan, or even with the loss of the ability to give rise to an identical twin.[41] The fact that early embryos can at times split into two genetically identical embryos does not mean that the embryo was not a single individual prior to becoming two individuals. The divisibility of early embryos is one of their unique biological features, comparable in some respects to the ability of animals like flatworms to grow as distinct individuals when cut in two.[42] As unusual as such biological divisibility may seem, there need be no confusion about whether a flatworm is a single biological individual prior to its being cut in two, just as there need be no confusion about the biological individuality of an embryo that has the potential to divide into genetically identical twins.

The British government’s report itself admitted that “biologically there is no one single identifiable stage in the development of the embryo beyond which the in vitro embryo should not be kept alive”[43] and that the decision to demarcate a limit was made “in order to allay public anxiety.”[44] So the fourteen-day limit on embryonic research is largely arbitrary, both morally and scientifically. And notwithstanding its wide adoption, it is not legally enforced in the United States. If promising research opportunities were to emerge that required experimenting on older embryos, it is likely that the ethical standards of the scientific community in the United States would shift to accommodate them, accepting research on older and older embryos.

Embryonic and fetal farming. One of the longstanding goals of regenerative medicine is to build organs from pluripotent stem cells. But growing organs from stem cells is an extremely complex matter, even more so than the difficult task of differentiating stem cells into particular cell types. Instead of deriving organs from stem cells, it may be more technically straightforward to culture embryos for longer periods of time. There are already biotechnology companies developing methods for transplanting organs from aborted fetuses,[45] but using cloning to produce genetically identical fetuses could well be a more attractive option. Cloned embryos could be grown past the fourteen-day limit to yield organ primordia, tissues, or stem cells that could be used for transplantation.

This possibility is less strange than it may seem. From a medical perspective, one reason to go in this direction is that transplantation of organ primordia to replace diseased organs seems to have therapeutic advantages over replacing diseased organs with healthy mature organs (such as in kidney transplants).[46] Researchers have explored this possibility by harvesting kidney primordia from aborted human fetuses and implanting them in immunodeficient mice, demonstrating that the organ primordia developed into semi-functioning kidneys.[47] The viable time to transplant kidney progenitors has been determined to be between 7 and 14 weeks of development.[48] There have already been several animal studies in which tissue from fetuses was harvested for the purpose of treating diseases in mature animals.[49] Considering the pressing need for viable human kidneys — there are more than 100,000 names on the U.S. waiting list as of this writing[50] — it is conceivable that in the future we will see increasing pressure to create cloned fetuses for the purpose of harvesting organs.

In 2006, Congress passed the Fetus Farming Prohibition Act to prohibit the deliberate production of fetuses for the sake of harvesting tissues or organs for medical or research purposes.[51] However, the law prohibits the use of fetuses gestated for research purposes, and so if researchers developed the means to grow embryos to the fetal stage in vitro, this law would likely not prohibit such actions.

Ectogenesis. The idea of growing prenatal human beings outside of the womb, or ectogenesis, is often associated in the public mind with science fiction, but in recent years it has been inching toward reality, as scientists have improved the ability to keep unborn human beings alive outside of the womb.[52] On the early side of the developmental spectrum, researchers have invented culturing methods that enable the growth of human embryos up to the fourteen-day limit.[53] And on the other side, we already have incubators for caring for premature infants born as early as 22 weeks.[54] Much of the research today is focused on developing technologies to save the lives of babies born prior to 24 weeks, before which the survival rate using existing incubators greatly decreases. However, some people are interested in developing artificial wombs to allow women who are unable to have children to do so without requiring a surrogate — or simply to allow women to have children without undergoing the burdens and inconveniences of biological pregnancy.[55]

Progress in cloning-for-biomedical-research could accelerate the move toward ectogenesis. The desire to obtain patient-specific organs for transplantation could make it attractive to grow cloned fetuses outside the womb. The Fetus Farming Prohibition Act, mentioned above, does not in fact prohibit growing fetuses outside of the womb in order to harvest their organs for research or transplantation.[56] Even if the law were repealed entirely, however, developing ectogenesis technologies may be easier than finding surrogates willing to become pregnant for the gruesome task of supplying doctors with spare parts.

If artificial womb technologies are developed significantly further, there would be far more harvesting of fetal tissues and organs, as the key technical obstacle to “fetal farming” would be removed. Further, the development of artificial wombs would potentially encourage people to argue that, in the interest of saving the lives of patients, we ought to permit the cloning and artificial cultivation of fetuses for the purpose of harvesting tissues.

Deliberately creating headless babies. It is with some trepidation that we raise the next scenario — already realized in animal experimentation — that might arise in an era of widespread cloning-for-biomedical-research: the possibility that cloning may lead to the deliberate creation of headless humans for growing organs.

The creation of headless clones as a source of organs seems gruesome and fantastic. But it also conforms all too well to some of the dominant attitudes in our society concerning the exploitation of prenatal human life. It is not hard to imagine a day when growing demand for sources of cells and organs for transplantation could lead to the creation of not just embryos but fetuses and infants; the deliberate engineering of these clones to lack human brains may be seen as a compassionate measure. Biologist and futurist Lee Silver endorsed the creation of headless clones in 1997, saying that he saw “nothing wrong, philosophically or rationally,” with the practice.[57]

This prospect may seem very far from any reputable scientific work, and indeed, it is far from clear that it will ever be feasible, technically. But scientists have spent decades studying the genes necessary for development, and in some cases the disruption of just one gene can prevent the development of whole organs or parts of the body. In 1995, scientists were able to create headless mouse fetuses by knocking out a single gene,[58] and research on the genetic basis of the development of the brain and head has continued in the years since.[59] Much of this work, conducted on animals, could provide medically useful knowledge of developmental disorders,[60] but it could also, at least theoretically, be used to produce headless human clones as well. So it is not inconceivable that scientists could create embryos that would be unable to develop certain organs or features that are taken by some to be definitive of human personhood, such as the brain, despite the fact that headless fetuses may sound like mere science fiction.

These entities would presumably lack many of the higher capacities of human beings, and might be thought by Silver and others as being less than human and having less than the moral standing of human fetuses, infants, or adults. In fact, this is one of the common arguments in favor of destroying embryos for research — embryos are clumps of cells that have not yet developed the brain functions necessary for thought and sensation that some see as underlying moral standing, and so it is morally justifiable to kill them to provide patients with medical treatments.[61] If it turns out that fetuses or infants are a more effective source of cells and organs for therapy, then ensuring that these fetuses will lack the capacities to think or feel will presumably, in this calculus, make them morally equivalent to the embryos we are already willing to kill in the name of medical research.

The repugnant thought of creating headless clones and the unsettling similarity of such an idea to how we already treat unborn human beings should give us reason to strengthen our commitment to the protection of unborn life by rejecting all forms of embryo exploitation now, before such grotesque possibilities come to seem more plausible.

Interspecies cloning. If cloning research programs continue to be frustrated by the lack of human egg cells, scientists may turn to creating cloned embryos by combining human cells with enucleated animal cells. Cell lines that showed quite similar properties to human embryonic stem cells have already been generated by transferring human somatic nuclei into rabbit oocytes, as long ago as 2003.[62] This kind of technique would result in embryonic stem cells that have the nuclear DNA of a human and the mitochondrial DNA of an animal.

Since interspecies cloning could potentially provide a means of producing patient-specific embryonic stem cells, many researchers have already proposed its use to make up for the difficulty of procuring human egg cells.[63] Interspecies cloning has also been suggested as a research tool to provide a better understanding of nuclear-mitochondrial interaction and to provide in vitro models to study late-onset diseases (such as Parkinson’s).[64]

It is still not clear if this kind of cloning will be an effective source of embryonic stem cells for either research or medicine. A report of the President’s Council on Bioethics in 2004 pointed out that more research would be required to know if mitochondrial proteins from animals persist in interspecies embryonic stem cells.[65] A 2009 study involving interspecies cloning using human neural stem cell nuclei and goat oocytes found that human mitochondrial proteins were expressed in the resulting cells, but that the incompatibility of the human genome with the goat cytoplasm meant the cells were not able properly to express genes necessary for mitochondrial function.[66]

Whether such methods could be effective or not, would they be morally better or worse than human cloning? Creating and killing human embryos is always wrong. The mixture of human and non-human life is in itself disturbing, although there are some cases in which mixing human and non-human cells or DNA can be morally acceptable. (A full moral analysis of interspecies research is beyond the scope of this report.) However, creating cloned embryos with uncertain standing as members of the human species in order to avoid the moral problems of human cloning is deeply troubling. Overcoming our sense of repugnance at the idea of creating human-animal hybrids only to use the creation of such hybrids as an excuse to overcome our moral judgments about the sanctity of human life would be not a form of sophisticated moral progress but would rather an example of moral evasion.

Artificial gametes. Another development that cloning-for-biomedical-research will both facilitate and increase the demand for is the creation of “artificial gametes” — egg and sperm cells, made to order. Researchers have laid out three potential applications for artificial gametes: to create in vitro models for the study of how human gametes develop and of germ-line diseases, to enable genetic manipulations of the human germ line, and to create a supply of gametes to use in research and assisted reproductive therapy.[67] But like interspecies cloning, the production of artificial gametes would provide a way to overcome the limited number of human eggs available for cloning research.

Already, researchers have used mouse embryonic stem cells to derive “sperm-like” and “egg-like” cells in vitro.[68] Researchers have also been able to derive cells that express markers similar to mature germ cells from human embryonic stem cells.[69] More recently, researchers were able to transform bone marrow stem cells into sperm-like cells.[70] Based on these studies and others, it is quite possible within the next several years that researchers will be able to derive large quantities of gamete cells from stem cells (either embryonic or induced pluripotent stem cells) in vitro.

While there are many related concerns about what such a technique might lead to, it is worth highlighting one in particular here. In vitro gametogenesis (IVG) increases our ability to design and produce the most genetically desirable gametes and embryos, because it greatly increases the quantity of gametes (especially oocytes) that can be used for IVF. Using such a technique to produce an embryo and create a human being would be a form of eugenic selection. Some bioethicists have instead proposed calling this kind of selection “procreative beneficence,” and have argued that “the ability to create large numbers of eggs or sperm through IVG greatly increases our capacity to select the best child possible.”[71] They point out that the mass production of artificial gametes would greatly increase the number of embryos available for selection. If gametes were used to create 10,000 embryos, they write, it is virtually guaranteed that parents will find an embryo that has their desired selection of, say, twenty different single-gene traits.[72]

Even if embryos are not created and destroyed on this scale, artificial gametes would still represent a significant increase in the eugenic ability to select desired traits in comparison to today’s techniques of IVF and preimplantation genetic diagnosis. And the use of artificial gametes in this way would result in the creation of untold thousands of embryos that will be discarded as failing to meet genetic quality-control standards.

Genetically engineered children. Creating genetically engineered children would be made much easier if cloning were a widely available technology. Cloning is already used by scientists to create genetically engineered animals, particularly large animals like pigs and cows.[73] One of the major challenges of producing genetically engineered animals is introducing specific genetic modifications into embryos without damaging or destroying them.[74] It is easier to introduce genetic modifications into somatic (“adult”) cells, and those modified somatic cells could be used through cloning to produce genetically modified offspring. For instance, scientists could keep cultures of skin cells in a dish and use genetic-modification techniques to introduce specific genetic changes, and then test the resulting cells to see if the genetic modifications have been successful — that is, to see whether the targeted genes have been modified and whether other sites in the genome may have been inadvertently modified. After this process of genetic modification and testing, the scientists could then use the modified somatic cells to create cloned embryos with specific desired genetic changes.

With the development of new genetic-modification techniques that offer increasingly precise means of editing the genome, demand may grow to use them to produce genetically modified children. In April 2015, Chinese researchers announced that they had for the first time genetically modified human embryos using a technique called CRISPR-Cas9,[75] and though the experiment was condemned by many in the scientific community,[76] some scientists have expressed a willingness to consider genetically engineering human beings with these methods.[77]

Genetic modification will always be a highly risky experiment — the human genome is immensely complex, and deliberately changing one gene is likely to have unpredictable effects. A full analysis of the risks and ethical implications of genetic-modification technology is beyond the scope of this report, but if the technology improves alongside research on human cloning, more and more scientists may be tempted to use the two in conjunction to produce genetically engineered children.

Another quite strange application of cloning combined with genetic engineering has been proposed by bioethicist Carson Strong in order to overcome ethical concerns arising from the fact that cloned children will not have unique genomes. In a 2005 article, Strong argued that by genetically modifying embryos, “the objection [to cloning] based on lack of uniqueness would no longer be applicable.”[78] Strong went on to speculate that genetic modification could be used “to give the child a nuclear DNA relationship to both members of an infertile couple” by introducing genetic modifications that would “duplicate certain selected genetic characteristics of the other member of the couple, such as hair or eye color,” so that “the child would possess nuclear genetic characteristics of both parents.”[79] This argument, however, fails to respond to cloning critics’ actual concerns. As we argued in Part Two, what is most repugnant about human cloning is the way it puts control over the genetic properties into the hands of the adults who choose to create them and distorts the relationship between the generations; Strong’s proposal to perform genetic modifications would only aggravate this problem.

Cloning and genetic engineering might also be combined with the creation of IVF embryos and embryonic stem cells. Consider this scenario: A couple who want a genetically modified child first use IVF to produce embryos, which they then destroy to derive embryonic stem cells, which can in turn be genetically modified and used to produce cloned offspring. Embryonic stem cells are already more efficient than ordinary somatic cells for cloning,[80] and the resulting cloned children would be genetically related to both “parents” (though, in some sense, the couple initiating this grisly reproductive procedure would be better understood to be the child’s grandparents, with the destroyed embryo from which the child is cloned being its parent).

Alternatives to Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research

Human cloning once appeared to be an essential part of the promising field of regenerative medicine. Without cloning, it was argued, researchers would be unable to create patient-specific stem cell lines, making it difficult to produce tissues for therapy or for studying particular diseases. As we described in our previous report The Stem Cell Debates: Lessons for Science and Politics, both the urgency and the promise of regenerative medicine were notoriously overhyped during the period from 2001 to 2006.[81] But that supposed urgency and promise put critics of embryo-destructive research in a difficult position: approving of cloning-for-biomedical-research would mean condoning the ethically unacceptable exploitation of women and of embryonic human life, but stopping cloning would mean forgoing a promising route toward treatments for numerous serious diseases and conditions.

This moral dilemma was never entirely stark — cloning was never more than a promising tool for research, not a certain source of cures. And there was always some hope that alternative forms of research that did not require the creation or destruction of embryos would be developed. Shinya Yamanaka’s 2006 discovery of a way to make induced pluripotent stem (iPS) cells in mice[82] (followed by their discovery in humans the next year[83]) gave the world hope that the medical promise of regenerative medicine could be achieved without pursuing ethically troubling research on human cloning.

And yet, while the availability of iPS cells has dampened interest in human cloning,[84] research on human cloning has not ceased (as shown by scientists’ successes in 2013 and 2014 in creating stem cells from cloned human embryos[85]).

Here we examine some of the reasons scientists have offered to justify continuing work on human cloning despite the availability of alternatives, and we show why the comparative advantages of pursuing human cloning are so minimal that they cannot surmount the ethical problems associated with that research.

Supposed advantages of cloning. Some scientists and advocates of embryo-destroying research believe that embryonic stem cells represent the “gold standard” for stem cell research.[86] Some have argued that cloning “mimics human physiology more faithfully” than the methods used to create iPS cells, because cloning “emulates normal fertilization.”[87] Two major studies were published in 2014 comparing stem cells produced through cloning to iPS cells; the first found that iPS cells were more likely to have epigenetic abnormalities,[88] but the second found that there were no significant epigenetic differences between iPS cells and embryonic stem cells produced through cloning.[89]

Cloning reprograms cells much faster than the methods for creating iPS cells, with cloning transforming the somatic cell into an embryo within hours, whereas iPS cells generally take weeks to reprogram.[90] Whether or not this makes iPS cells more vulnerable to the accumulation of genetic defects is largely unknown.[91] Some scientists have suggested that, because the production of iPS cells involves many rounds of cell division, iPS cells may have a higher risk of proliferating like cancerous cells than stem cells produced through cloning.[92] This higher risk of cancerous proliferation for iPS cells remains largely speculative, however.[93] And as shown by a recent study reporting that iPS cells and cloning-derived stem cells have similar numbers of mutations,[94] the risk of becoming cancerous may not be substantially different between iPS cells and stem cells produced through cloning.

Advantages of iPS cells over cloned stem cells. The difficulty of procuring human eggs means that cloning-based therapies may never be viable as mainstream medical treatments. Extrapolating from recent experiments, it appears that roughly a dozen or more eggs would be required to use cloning to create a single stem cell line.[95] And because each cycle of egg-retrieval procures an average of around twelve eggs,[96] about one retrieval procedure would be required for there to be enough eggs to give a good chance of deriving a therapeutic stem cell line to treat one patient. Further research may improve the efficiency of this process, but working from this fairly conservative calculation, in order for cloning to become the basis for widespread stem cell therapies — say, providing personalized stem cells to 100,000 patients per year — there would have to be approximately 100,000 egg-retrieval procedures per year. This would likely only be possible if there were a massive market for human eggs, on the order of hundreds of millions of dollars per year.[97] Alternatively, artificial eggs might someday be produced, as discussed above. Either of these scenarios would be morally troubling and practically complex, and unlikely to come to pass without major scientific and social changes.

The impracticality of a medical cloning enterprise of course does not provide justification for eschewing cloning research per se; it merely implies that we should not dedicate our medical resources toward cloning-derived stem cell therapies. It makes much more sense to dedicate those resources to therapies based on iPS cells, which do not require human eggs, thus avoiding the risks to women and concerns about exploitation that an egg market would entail. The potential for widespread availability is one of the most significant practical and moral advantages of iPS cells.

From a therapeutic perspective, a further advantage of iPS cells over cloning-derived stem cells is that the latter may have a higher chance of triggering an immune response.[98] Even though cloning-derived stem cells used for therapy would have the same nuclear DNA as the patient, they would have different mitochondrial DNA, and a recent study in mice showed that this difference in mitochondrial DNA can cause immune reactions.[99] (While iPS cells also sometimes cause immune responses, they would not have immune problems connected to differences in mitochondrial DNA.) Relatedly, there may be immune reactions and other problems resulting from “heteroplasmy” in stem cells derived from cloning — mitochondrial DNA incidentally brought along with the somatic-cell nucleus that differs from the bulk of the mitochondrial DNA found in the egg cell.[100]

Do we need to pursue both lines of research? When iPS cells were discovered, some scientists expected that cloning, in the words of one journalist, “may one day become a history lesson.”[101] However, with the first successful derivation of stem cells from human cloning in 2013, the scientific community has once again come to see cloning as an important research program,[102] a view reinforced by the successful cloning experiments in 2014.[103] Many scientists believe that both lines of research should be pursued, arguing that cloning could improve our understanding of how to produce iPS cells.[104]

One reason that has been given in support of simultaneously pursuing cloning and iPS cell research is that the former might indirectly make the latter more effective. Research on cloning could, some scientists have argued, be used to improve the techniques for producing iPS cells.[105] This stands to reason: there are obvious similarities between the fields, both of which involve reprogramming cells, and it would be surprising if there weren’t at least some findings of value to both.

Still, the crossover of knowledge between cloning research and iPS cell research should not be overstated. In a 2011 paper, bioethicist Insoo Hyun claimed that Shinya Yamanaka, the first researcher to produce iPS cells, may have used results of cloning research to identify factors that can be used to improve iPS cell reprogramming.[106] But the influence of the cloning study on the Yamanaka paper in question was minimal.[107] (In fact, the insights about cloning that Yamanaka depended on could justly be attributed to knowledge that dates back to the early 1960s, when John Gurdon first performed cloning experiments with frogs; as we noted in Part One, Yamanaka and Gurdon shared a Nobel Prize in 2012 for their discoveries related to cell reprogramming.) Moreover, in the Yamanaka study Hyun points to, the scientists who were supposedly dependent on the findings of cloning research still needed to go through a library of 1,473 transcription factors to identify a particularly effective factor for reprogramming somatic cells[108] — so it is difficult to believe that advances in cloning research contributed much to that work on iPS cells.

The idea that cloning research is necessary for progress in iPS cell research is something of a convenient myth. If all cloning research stopped, iPS cell research would hardly grind to a halt. And of course, if only human cloning research were stopped, the basic science of reprogramming could still be studied through animal cloning — indeed, the cloning study Hyun refers to which supposedly influenced Yamanaka was conducted with mice, not humans.

The issue of whether to pursue both iPS cell research and cloning research must hinge on whether the potential knowledge acquired through cloning overrides the ethical concerns raised by cloning, including especially the destruction of human embryos.

If we regard embryos as having inherent value — a dignity or sanctity linked to their status as human organisms at the earliest stage of life — then we ought to be committed at least to the claim that there should be no unnecessary destruction of human embryos. It is worth noting that this point has been acknowledged even by some supporters of embryonic research. For instance, the Ethics Advisory Board counseling the U.S. government on embryo research in 1979 wrote that “the human embryo is entitled to profound respect.”[109] An influential 1984 British report on embryo research also found that “the human embryo is entitled to some added measure of respect beyond that accorded to other animal subjects.”[110] Although this concept of “respect” is notoriously fuzzy and often has been used merely as rhetorical cover,[111] supporters of embryo research will sometimes gesture at its practical consequences. To give but one example, the bioethicist Dan W. Brock, a supporter of embryo-destroying research including cloning-for-biomedical-research, has written that

human embryos could be shown the special respect that [their] intermediate moral status requires by limiting their use to equally important human purposes. That special respect would justify guidelines limiting embryos’ use and destruction to research with reasonable promise of alleviating serious human disease and suffering.[112]

Anyone who accepts the position that the human embryo has at least some intrinsic value can only condone the destruction of human embryos if it is necessary for achieving some good of greater value. Since some say that the future medical benefit of stem cells provides such a value, this potential benefit is usually taken to justify the destruction of human embryos in scientific research.

However, in iPS cells we have a means of developing stem cell therapies that does not require the destruction of embryos. While iPS cells may have certain limitations, as reviewed earlier in this section, those limitations do not appear to undermine the merit of the technique. Anyone who regards the human embryo as having some kind of non-instrumental value must recognize that cloning-for-biomedical-research should not continue.

Altered nuclear transfer. Another widely discussed alternative to cloning-for-biomedical-research is altered nuclear transfer (ANT), a proposal developed Dr. William B. Hurlbut as an outgrowth of his work as a member of the President’s Council on Bioethics.[113] As the name suggests, ANT is similar to somatic cell nuclear transfer, the technique used for cloning, but it would involve modifications either to the oocyte, the somatic-cell nucleus, or both, so that the nuclear transfer operation would produce a biological artifact that could serve as a source of pluripotent stem cells, but would not be an embryo. Hurlbut prefers to call the products of ANT simply “entities” instead of embryos, and has said that they would lack the moral status of a human embryo since they would have “no inherent principle of unity, no coherent drive in the direction of the mature human form.”[114] If he is correct to say that these entities lack the integrated organization of a living being — that they are equivalent to disordered collections of cells that result from failed fertilization like teratomas or hydatidiform moles[115] — then ANT could offer a morally acceptable alternative to cloning for producing genetically identical pluripotent stem cells, since it would not require the destruction of human embryos.

The methods of ANT were designed through a combination of moral reasoning and philosophical and scientific reflection about the meaning of embryonic human life. ANT therefore offers not only a promising alternative to the particular moral problems of cloning-for-biomedical-research, but also holds out the promise of cooperative dialogue between scientists and moral philosophers, recognizing that moral philosophy concerning human life must be informed by science, and also that, to borrow medical ethicist Paul Ramsey’s remark about physicians, scientists “must in greater measure become moral philosophers.”[116]

Not everyone agrees with Hurlbut that the products of ANT are not embryos. In a 2004 letter to the New England Journal of Medicine, three Harvard-based stem cell researchers argued that the presence of defects could not settle the ethical question concerning the moral status of the embryo.[117] They argue that the inherent principle of unity and coherent organismal drive that Hurlbut cited “are ill-defined concepts with no clear biologic meaning.”[118] Whether or not these concepts are scientifically meaningful is at the crux of the debate over ANT, and indeed of the debate over human embryo research more generally. Can science tell us whether embryos are biological individuals with lives that begin at conception, or must an empirical biological science reject such questions about what biological entities are as scientifically meaningless and focus only on what can be done with biological materials?

In principle, by modifying key developmental genes in the oocyte and in the somatic cell, ANT could produce an entity that will not have the organized unity of a human embryo. As biologist Maureen L. Condic has argued, ANT results in the production of entities unable to undertake “the first globally coordinated event in human development, the formation of trophoblast and inner cell mass lineages,” which is “the earliest act of the embryo qua embryo.”[119] Addressing gravely important considerations like these, which arise from a confrontation with the question of what the embryo is, should be a much higher priority for developmental biologists and embryologists as they seek to develop new biotechnological powers over human life.

As of this writing, no attempts at ANT have yet been reported with humans, although there have been some attempts involving animals. In 2006, biologists Alexander Meissner and Rudolf Jaenisch attempted to use one ANT method with mice. The researchers noted that the products of ANT were “inherently unable to implant into the uterus” because they lacked the ability to form the outer layer of the embryo necessary for implantation.[120] The authors also observed that the products of ANT lacked a number of features necessary for embryonic development.[121] The scientists were nonetheless able to derive pluripotent stem cells, holding out the promise that, should there ever be general acceptance that the products of ANT are not embryos, ANT could be a useful and morally acceptable alternative to cloning.[122]

Are embryonic stem cells a “gold standard”? Many writers and scientists describe embryonic stem cells as the gold standard for stem cells.[123] Because cloning-derived stem cells come from embryos, the notion of the gold standard is sometimes taken to imply that they are of a higher quality than iPS cells.[124]

Both of those assumptions — that embryonic stem cells represent a gold standard for comparison and that cloning-derived stem cells are functionally superior to iPS cells — are scientifically dubious. To understand why, let us begin by pointing out that the term “embryonic stem cells” is something of a misnomer. Unlike somatic (“adult”) stem cells, which are found in the body — so, for example, neural stem cells can be found in the brain — embryonic stem cells are not found in the embryo. As Rudolf Jaenisch stated at a meeting of the President’s Council on Bioethics in 2003, embryonic stem cells “have no counterpart” in actual animal embryos.[125] Rather, they are made out of cells found in embryos. It would be more precise to call them “embryo-derived stem cells.”[126] This terminology would highlight the fact that what we refer to as “embryonic stem cells” do not occur in nature — they are artificially produced. Extracting cells from the inner cell mass and culturing them in an artificial tissue-culture environment induces changes to the cells. As some developmental biologists have emphasized, the notion that embryonic stem cells represent an in vitro equivalent to cells of the inner cell mass is unjustified, since embryonic stem cells have a number of important properties not found in any cells of the early embryo.[127]

One such useful property is long-term self-renewal. In a natural bodily setting, no embryonic cell demonstrates long-term self-renewal.[128] But embryonic stem cells (and iPS cells) in their artificial environment do. As one review put it,

embryonic cells, once brought into tissue culture, are exposed to numerous extrinsic signals to which they never would be exposed … in vivo. ES [embryonic stem] cells certainly adapt to selective tissue culture conditions and acquire novel functions that allow them to proliferate in an undifferentiated state indefinitely, and, because of this, ES cells are in some sense tissue-culture artifacts.[129]

The exposure to artificial tissue-culture conditions is an inevitable aspect of embryonic stem cells (as well as iPS cells). Embryonic stem cells are not somehow more natural than iPS cells; both are shaped in important ways by technical intervention.

Furthermore, there is little reason to treat embryonic stem cells produced through cloning as a gold standard for patient-specific stem cells. Cloning-derived stem cells and iPS cells should be compared on dimensions pertinent to medical therapy, such as the immune reactions they instigate and their ability to successfully differentiate into various useful cell types. While the degree of similarity between embryo-derived and non-embryo-derived stem cells may turn out to be an indicator of these qualities, the degree of similarity itself cannot be the ultimate basis for evaluating the therapeutic prospects of stem cells.

Evidence from studies looking at the clinically relevant features of stem cells suggests that iPS cells could be effective replacements for embryonic stem cells. For example, in a paper published in 2014, researcher Douglas Melton and his colleagues reported developing a method for making insulin-producing cells on the scale necessary to treat type 1 diabetes. Melton’s team was able to use both human embryonic stem cells and iPS cells to generate these insulin-producing cells, indicating that iPS cells were at least adequate for this clinical purpose.[130] In September 2014, scientists in Japan began clinical trials for a treatment for macular degeneration, a condition that can lead to blindness, using cells derived from human iPS cells.[131] While the results of these trials have not yet been published, data from pre-clinical studies on the safety and quality of iPS cells is promising, with experiments in animal models showing that iPS cells seem not to cause tumors or immune rejection, two of the main safety concerns.[132] The actual use of iPS cells in therapy and in research strongly suggests that they represent a viable alternative to using cloning to produce patient-specific stem cells.

Conclusion: Scientific Research and the Need for Ethics

The discovery of human embryonic stem cells in 1998, just a year after the cloning of Dolly was announced, transformed the debate over human cloning. The project of regenerative medicine seemed to give cloning a morally serious purpose, moving it from the controversial fringes of reproductive autonomy to the heart of the medical research enterprise. By 2004, although scientific success with human cloning was still very limited, prominent supporters of embryonic stem cell research were calling for the mass-production of cloned human embryos for spare parts.[133] Although the discovery of induced pluripotent stem cells in 2006 seemed to have eliminated the need for cloning-for-biomedical-research, and numerous scientists turned away from cloning in favor of the more practical and ethical new technique, scientific work on human cloning did not cease, as the experiments in 2013 and 2014 demonstrate. For scientists who believe that the destruction of human embryos is morally acceptable, cloning remains another promising avenue of research. For such scientists, even if human cloning no longer seems necessary, so long as it is possible it should still be pursued.

While the availability of alternative sources of pluripotent stem cells makes cloning-for-biomedical-research unnecessary, it does not make prohibitions against human cloning unnecessary — rather, it makes the decision to prohibit human cloning easier. We no longer face the hard choice of either forgoing promising medical research or maintaining some level of commitment to the sanctity of human life. Scientific progress has, in this case, given us the opportunity to draw apart the goods of medical progress from the harm of destroying human life, but we must take advantage of this opportunity with resolute political action — prohibiting all forms of human cloning now. Doing so will require careful attention to the past two decades of policy and political debates over cloning legislation and regulation, a matter to which we turn next.


Notes
[1] Center for Genetics and Society staff, “CGS Summary of Public Opinion Polls” (online publication), February 4, 2014, http://www.geneticsandsociety.org/article.php?id=401.
[2] These legislative efforts are discussed in Part Four below.
[3] Robert P. George and Christopher Tollefsen, Embryo: A Defense of Human Life (New York: Doubleday, 2008): 4.
[4] Scott F. Gilbert, Anna L. Tyler, and Emily J. Zackin, Bioethics and the New Embryology (Sunderland, Mass.: W.H. Freeman/Sinauer Associates, 2005), 40.
[5] President’s Council on Bioethics, Reproduction and Responsibility (Washington, D.C., 2004), 29, available at https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcbe/reports/reproductionandresponsibility/.
[7] Office of the Secretary of State of the State of California, “Text of Proposed Laws: Proposition 71,” Official Voter Information Guide, 147, http://vote2004.sos.ca.gov/voterguide/english.pdf.
[8] C. Caligara et al., “The effect of repeated controlled ovarian stimulation in donors,” Human Reproduction 16, no. 11 (2001): 2320, http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humrep/16.11.2320.
[9] C.O. Nastri, “Ovarian hyperstimulation syndrome: pathophysiology, staging, prediction and prevention,” Ultrasound in Obstetrics and Gynecology 45 (2015): 377, http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/uog.14684.
[10] Ibid., 380.
[11] Annick Delvigne and Serge Rozenberg, “Epidemiology and Prevention of Ovarian Hyperstimulation Syndrome (OHSS): A Review,” Human Reproduction Update 8, no. 6 (2002): 559, http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/humupd/8.6.559.
[12] Salem A. El-Shawarby et al., “A review of complications following transvaginal oocyte retrieval for in-vitro fertilization,” Human Fertility 7, no. 2 (2004): 127–133.
[13] The underlying causes of infertility affecting patients undergoing IVF or ovulation induction may also aggravate the risks of ovarian hyperstimulation syndrome (OHSS) and some complications from egg-retrieval surgery, and there is evidence that pregnancy may also be a risk factor for OHSS. Healthy egg providers who do not become pregnant following ovarian stimulation may therefore be at a lower risk of developing OHSS. See Brooke Ellison and Jaymie Meliker, “Assessing the Risk of Ovarian Hyperstimulation Syndrome in Egg Donation: Implications for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research,” American Journal of Bioethics 11, no. 9 (2011): 26, http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2011.593683; Klaus Fiedler and Diego Ezcurra, “Predicting and preventing ovarian hyperstimulation syndrome (OHSS): the need for individualized not standardized treatment,” Reproductive Biology and Endocrinology 10, no. 32 (2012): 3, http://dx.doi.org/10.1186/1477-7827-10-32.
[14] See, for example, California’s laws on this matter: California Health and Safety Code, Division 106, §§125350–125355, S.B. 18 (2005), http://leginfo.legislature.ca.gov/faces/codes_displayText.xhtml?lawCode=HSC&division=106.&title=&part=5.5.&chapter=2.
[15] National Research Council, Final Report of the National Academies’ Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research Advisory Committee and 2010 Amendments to the National Academies’ Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research (Washington, D.C.: The National Academies Press 2010): 27, http://www.nap.edu/openbook.php?record_id=12923.
[16] Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine, “Financial compensation for oocyte donors,” Fertility and Sterility 88, no. 22 (2007): 308, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.fertnstert.2007.01.104.
[17] International Society for Stem Cell Research (ISSCR), Guidelines for the Conduct of Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research, December 21, 2006, http://www.isscr.org/docs/default-source/hesc-guidelines/isscrhescguidelines2006.pdf.
[18] George Q. Daley et al., “The ISSCR Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research,” Science 315 (February 2, 2007): 604, http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.1139337.
[19] Susan L. Crockin, “A Legal Defense for Compensating Research Egg Donors,” Cell Stem Cell 6, no. 2 (2010): 99, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2010.01.010.
[20] Insoo Hyun, “Fair payment or undue inducement?,” Nature 442, no. 7103 (2006): 629–630, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/442629a.
[21] David Magnus and Mildred K. Cho, “Issues in Oocyte Donation for Stem Cell Research,” Science 308, no. 5729 (2005): 1747–1748, http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.1114454; Dieter Egli et al., “Impracticality of Egg Donor Recruitment in the Absence of Compensation,” Cell Stem Cell 9, no. 4 (2011): 293–294, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2011.08.002.
[22] Robert Klitzman and Mark V. Sauer, “Payment of egg donors in stem cell research in the USA,” Reproductive Biomedicine Online 18, no. 5 (2009): 606, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S1472-6483(10)60002-8.
[23] Hyun, “Fair payment or undue inducement?”
[24] Françoise Baylis and Carolyn McLeod, “The stem cell debate continues: The buying and selling of eggs for research,” Journal of Medical Ethics 33, no. 12 (2007): 726–731, http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/jme.2007.022129.
[25] Ibid., 729.
[26] Ibid., 729–730.
[27] Kathrin Braun and Susanne Schultz, “Oöcytes for research: inspecting the commercialization continuum,” New Genetics and Society 31, no. 2 (2012): 135–157, http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/14636778.2011.603953; Carlene Hempel, “Golden Eggs: Drowning in credit-card debt and student loans, young women are selling their eggs for big payoffs. But can they really make the right medical and moral decisions when they’re tempted with $15,000?,” The Boston Globe, June 25, 2006, http://www.boston.com/news/globe/magazine/articles/2006/06/25/golden_eggs/.
[28] Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine, “Financial compensation of oocyte donors,” 306.
[29] Michelle L. Sparman, Masahito Tachibana, and Shoukhrat M. Mitalipov, “Cloning of non-human primates: the road ‘less traveled by,’” International Journal of Developmental Biology 54, no. 11–12 (2010): 1671–1678 http://dx.doi.org/10.1387/ijdb.103196ms.
[30] Hans Jonas, “Biological Engineering: A Preview,” in Philosophical Essays: From Ancient Creed to Technological Man (New York: Atropos Press, 2010), 143.
[31] Ron Reagan, speech at the Democratic National Convention, July 27, 2004, transcript at PresidentialRhetoric.com, http://www.presidentialrhetoric.com/campaign/dncspeeches/reagan.html, video at C-SPAN, http://www.c-spanvideo.org/program/Day2Ev/start/11366/stop/11940.
[32] Australia, Parliament, Prohibition of Human Cloning for Reproduction and the Regulation of Human Embryo Research Amendment Act 2006, no. 172, §14, 2006, http://www.comlaw.gov.au/Details/C2006A00172.
[33] Assisted Human Reproductive Act, Statues of Canada 2004, c. 2, http://laws-lois.justice.gc.ca/eng/acts/A-13.4/page-2.html.
[34] Indian Council of Medical Research, National Guidelines for Stem Cell Research, December 2013, 10, http://icmr.nic.in/guidelines/NGSCR 2013.pdf.
[35] Japan, Ministry of Education, Culture, Sports, Science and Technology (MEXT), Guidelines for the Derivation and Utilization of Human Embryonic Stem Cells (Hito-ES saibou no jyuritsu oyobi siyou ni kansuru sisin), art. 6, enacted September 25, 2001, http://www.lifescience.mext.go.jp/files/pdf/32_88.pdf (Japanese), http://www.lifescience.mext.go.jp/files/pdf/32_90.pdf (English).
[36] United Kingdom, Parliament, Human Fertilization and Embryology Act (1990), c. 37, as amended by Human Fertilization and Embryology Act (2008), c. 22, 4A, http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/2008/22/contents.
[37] Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine, “Donating embryos for human embryonic stem cell research: a committee opinion,” Fertility and Sterility 100, no. 4 (2013): 936m http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.fertnstert.2013.08.038.
[38] National Academies of Science, Final Report of The National Academies’ Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research Advisory Committee and 2010 Amendments to The National Academies’ Guidelines for Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research, 23.
[39] California Institute for Regenerative Medicine, “Reformatted CIRM Medical and Ethical Standards Regulations,” August 25, 2011, §100030, https://www.cirm.ca.gov/sites/default/files/files/funding_page/Reformatted_MES_Regs.pdf.
[40] United Kingdom Department of Health & Social Security, Report of the Committee of Inquiry Into Human Fertilisation and Embryology (London: Her Majesty’s Stationery Office, 1984): 66.
[41] Patrick Lee and Robert P. George, “The First Fourteen Days of Human Life,” The New Atlantis 13 (Summer 2006): 61–67, http://44.239.21.170/publications/the-first-fourteen-days-of-human-life.
[42] Jeremy P. Brockes and Anoop Kumar “Comparative Aspects of Animal Regeneration,” Annual Reviews of Cellular and Developmental Biology 24, (2008): 525–549, http://dx.doi.org/10.1146/annurev.cellbio.24.110707.175336.
[43] United Kingdom Department of Health & Social Security, Report of the Committee of Inquiry Into Human Fertilisation and Embryology, 65.
[44] Ibid.
[45] N.K. Chang et al., “Arterial Flow Regulator Enables Transplantation and Growth of Human Fetal Kidneys in Rats,” American Journal of Transplantation 15, no. 6, (June 2015): 1692–1700, http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/ajt.13149.
[46] These advantages are discussed in Marc R. Hammerman, “Xenotransplantation of pancreatic and kidney primordia — Where do we stand?,” Transplant Immunology 21, no. 2 (2009): 93–100, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.trim.2008.10.007.
[47] Benjamin Dekel et al., “Human and porcine early kidney precursors as a new source for transplantation,” Nature Medicine 9, no. 1 (2002): 53–60, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nm812.
[48] Ibid., 53.
[49] For example, see Robert Lanza et al., “Long-Term Bovine Hematopoietic Engraftment with Clone-Derived Stem Cells,” Cloning and Stem Cells 7, no. 2 (2005): 95–106, http://dx.doi.org/10.1089/clo.2005.7.95.
[50] U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, “Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network Data,” http://optn.transplant.hrsa.gov/converge/data/default.asp.
[51] Fetus Farming Prohibition Act of 2006, Public Law 109-242, U.S. Statutes at Large 120 (2006): 570–571.
[52] Christine Rosen, “Why Not Artificial Wombs?,” The New Atlantis 3 (Fall 2003): 67–76, http://44.239.21.170/publications/why-not-artificial-wombs.
[53] P. Chavatte-Palmer, R. Lévy, and P. Boileau, “Reproduction without a uterus? State of the art of ectogenesis,” Gynecologie, Obstetrique & Fertilite 40, no. 11 (2012): 695–697, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.gyobfe.2012.09.008.
[54] Matthew A. Rysavy et al., “Between-Hospital Variation in Treatment and Outcomes in Extremely Preterm Infants,” New England Journal of Medicine 372, 1807 (2015), http://dx.doi.org/10.1056/NEJMoa1410689.
[55] It has been argued, for instance, that such burdens constitute an injustice, and that because it might be possible to remedy this injustice in the future, we should pursue all means of doing so. Anna Smajdor, “The Moral Imperative for Ectogenesis,” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 16, no. 3 (2007): 336–345, http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0963180107070405.
[56] Fetus Farming Prohibition Act of 2006, op. cit.
[57] Steve Connor, “Cloners hatch headless embryos of mice — and men?,” The Sunday Times, December 22, 1997: World 7.
[58] William Shawlot and Richard R. Behringer, “Requirement for LIml in head-organizer function,” Nature 374 (1994): 425–430, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/374425a0.
[59] Cynthia Lilian Andoniadou and Juan Pedro Martinez-Barbera, “Developmental mechanisms directing early anterior forebrain specification in vertebrates,” Cellular and Molecular Life Sciences 70, no. 20 (2013): 3739–3752, http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s00018-013-1269-5.
[60] J.T. Wigle and D.D. Eisenstat, “Homeobox genes in vertebrate forebrain development and disease,” Clinical Genetics 73 (2008): 212–226, http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1399-0004.2008.00967.x.
[61] See, for example, Scott F. Gilbert, Anna L. Tyler, and Emily J. Zackin, Bioethics and the New Embryology, (Sunderland, Mass.: W.H. Freeman and Sinauer Associates 2005): 44; see also Michael S. Gazzaniga, The Ethical Brain (New York: Dana Press, 2005), 7.
[62] Chen Ying et al., “Embryonic stem cells generated by nuclear transfer of human somatic nuclei into rabbit oocytes,” Cell Research 13, no. 4 (2003): 251–263, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/sj.cr.7290170a.
[63] For example, see Stephen Minger, “Interspecies SCNT-derived human embryos-a new way forward for regenerative medicine,” Regenerative Medicine 2, no. 2 (2007): 103–106, http://dx.doi.org/10.2217/17460751.2.2.103; Zeki Beyhan, et al, “Interspecies Nuclear Transfer: Implications for Embryonic Stem Cell Biology,” Cell Stem Cell 1, no. 5 (2007): 502–512, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2007.10.009; Justin C. St John et al., “Law should recognize value of interspecies embryos,” Nature 451, no. 7179 (2008): 627, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/451627a.
[64] Zeki Beyhan, Amy E. Iager, and Jose B. Cibelli, “Interspecies Nuclear Transfer: Implications for Embryonic Stem Cell Biology,” Cell Stem Cell 1, no. 5 (2007): 502–512, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2007.10.009.
[65] President’s Council on Bioethics, Monitoring Stem Cell Research, Washington, D.C. (January 2004), 129, http://bioethics.georgetown.edu/pcbe/reports/stemcell/pcbe_final_version_monitoring_stem_cell_research.pdf.
[66] Hong-ying Sha et al., “Fates of donor and recipient mitochondrial DNA during generation of interspecies SCNT-derived human ES-like cells,” Cloning and Stem Cells 11, no. 4 (2009): 497–507, http://dx.doi.org/10.1089/clo.2009.0021.
[67] Hannah Bourne, Thomas Douglas, and Julian Savulescu, “Procreative beneficence and in vitro gametogenesis,” Monash Bioethics Review 30, no. 2 (2012): 29–48, http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3590899/; Kinarm Ko et al., “In vitro derivation of germ cells from embryonic stem cells,” Frontiers in Bioscience (Landmark Edition) 15 (2009): 46–56, http://dx.doi.org/10.2741/3605.
[68] Karin Hübner et al., “Derivation of Oocytes from Mouse Embryonic Stem Cells,” Science 300, no. 5623 (2003): 1251–1256, http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.1083452; Niels Geijsen et al., “Derivation of embryonic germ cells and male gametes from embryonic stem cells,” Nature 427, no. 6970 (2003): 148–154, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nature02247.
[69] Amander T. Clark et al., “Spontaneous differentiation of germ cells from human embryonic stem cells in vitro,” Human Molecular Genetics 13, no. 7 (2004): 727–739, http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/hmg/ddh088.
[70] Nadja Drusenheimer et al., “Putative human male germ cells from bone marrow stem cells,” Society of Reproduction and Fertility supplement 63 (2006): 69–76, http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/17566262.
[71] Hannah Bourne et al. “Procreative beneficence and in vitro gametogenesis,” 2.
[72] Ibid.
[73] Cesare Galli et al., “Somatic Cell Nuclear Transfer and Transgenesis in Large Animals: Current and Future Insights,” Reproduction in Domestic Animals 47, no. s3 (2012): 2, http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1439-0531.2012.02045.x.
[74] Ibid., 2–11; Wilfried A. Kues and Heiner Niemann, “Advances in farm animal transgenesis,” Preventive Veterinary Medicine 102, no. 2 (2011): 146, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.prevetmed.2011.04.009.
[75] Puping Liang et al., “CRISPR/Cas9-mediated gene editing in human tripronuclear zygotes,” Protein & Cell 6, no. 5, (2015): 363–372, http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s13238-015-0153-5.
[76] See, for example, Edward Lanphier et al., “Don’t edit the human germ line,” Nature 519, no. 7544 (2015): 410, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/519410a; Rob Stein, “Critics Lash Out At Chinese Scientists Who Edited DNA In Human Embryos,” NPR, April 23, 2015, http://www.npr.org/sections/health-shots/2015/04/23/401655818/critics-lash-out-at-chinese-scientists-who-edited-dna-in-human-embryos.
[77] David Cyranoski, “Ethics of embryo editing divides scientists,” Nature 519, no. 7543 (2015): 272, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/519272a.
[78] Carson Strong, “Reproductive cloning combined with genetic modification,” Journal of Medical Ethics 31, no. 11, (2005): 655.
[79] Ibid.
[80] David Humpherys et al., “Abnormal gene expression in cloned mice derived from embryonic stem cell and cumulus cell nuclei,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 99.20 (2002): 12889, http://dx.doi.org/10.1073/pnas.192433399; William M. Rideout et al., “Generation of mice from wild-type and targeted ES cells by nuclear cloning,” Nature Genetics 24, no. 2 (2000): 109–110, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/72753.
[81] Witherspoon Council on Ethics and the Integrity of Science, “The Stem Cell Debates: Lessons for Science and Politics,” The New Atlantis 34 (Winter 2012): 1–146, http://44.239.21.170/publications/the-stem-cell-debates-lessons-for-science-and-politics.
[82] Kazutoshi Takahashi and Shinya Yamanaka, “Induction of Pluripotent Stem Cells from Mouse Embryonic and Adult Fibroblast Cultures by Defined Factors,” Cell 126, no. 4 (2006): 663–676, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cell.2006.07.024.
[83] Kazutoshi Takahashi et al., “Induction of Pluripotent Stem Cells from Adult Human Fibroblasts by Defined Factors,” Cell 131, no. 5 (2007): 861–872, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cell.2007.11.019; Junying Yu et al., “Induced Pluripotent Stem Cell Lines Derived from Human Somatic Cells,” Science 318, no. 5858 (2007): 1917–1920, http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.1151526.
[84] Sally Lehrman, “No More Cloning Around,” Scientific American 299 (July 21, 2008): 100–102, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/scientificamerican0808-100.
[85] Masahito Tachibana et al., “Human Embryonic Stem Cells Derived by Somatic Cell Nuclear Transfer,” Cell 153, iss. 6 (June 6, 2013): 1228–1238, dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cell.2013.05.006; Mitsutoshi Yamada et al., “Human oocytes reprogram adult somatic nuclei of a type 1 diabetic to diploid pluripotent stem cells,” Nature 510 (June 26, 2014): 533–538, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nature13287; Young Gie Chung et al., “Human Somatic Cell Nuclear Transfer Using Adult Cells,” Cell Stem Cell 14 (2014): 777–780, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2014.03.015.
[86] See, for example, Andrea Gawrylewski, “Embryonic stem cells still gold standard,” The Scientist (June 13, 2008), http://www.the-scientist.com/?articles.view/articleno/26495/title/embryonic-stem-cells-still-gold-standard/.
[87] Alan Colman and Justine Burley, “Human Somatic Cell Reprogramming: Does the Egg Know Best?,” Cell Stem Cell 15 (November 6, 2014): 531, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2014.10.011.
[88] Hong Ma et al., “Abnormalities in human pluripotent cells due to reprogramming mechanisms,” Nature 511 (July 10, 2014): 177–183, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nature13551.
[89] Bjarki Johannesson et al., “Comparable Frequencies of Coding Mutations and Loss of Imprinting in Human Pluripotent Cells Derived by Nuclear Transfer and Defined Factors,” Cell Stem Cell 15, no. 5 (2014): 634–642, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2014.10.002.
[90] Guangjin Pan et al., “Somatic cell reprogramming for regenerative medicine: SCNT vs. iPS cells,” BioEssays 34, no. 6 (2012): 472–476, http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/bies.201100174.
[91] Ibid., 474.
[92] Because the dedifferentiation process required for producing iPS cells is long and influenced by cell proliferation (as the cells that are positively selected for are those that grow quickly), iPS cells may be more likely than cloning-derived stem cells to become tumorigenic.
[93] Ignacio Sancho-Martinez and J. Izpisua Belmonte, “Will SCNT-ESCs Be Better than iPS cells for Personalized Regenerative Medicine?,” Cell Stem Cell 13, no. 2 (2013): 141–142, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2013.07.013.
[94] Bjarki Johannesson et al., “Comparable Frequencies of Coding Mutations and Loss of Imprinting in Human Pluripotent Cells Derived by Nuclear Transfer and Defined Factors,” Cell Stem Cell 15, no. 5 (2014): 634–642, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2014.10.002.
[95] This estimate is calculated from the rate of deriving stem cell lines via cloning in three papers that have produced human cloning-derived stem cells. In each paper the rate of deriving stem cell lines after cloning was approximately 10 percent. If this figure is used to calculate the probability of success according to a binomial distribution, it would require 22 eggs to have a 90 percent chance of deriving at least one stem cell line. To be sure, our estimate is necessarily based on very limited data. It is possible that the efficiency of cloning could be higher. But for the purposes of deriving embryonic stem cell lines for therapy, at least one egg-collection cycle will likely be required for each patient. Even if one egg-collection cycle produces more eggs than are needed to create an embryonic stem cell line for a particular patient, it would be difficult to coordinate the use of the remaining egg cells for cloning procedures for other patients. (The papers used to arrive at the above figures are: Masahito Tachibana et al., “Human Embryonic Stem Cells Derived by Somatic Cell Nuclear Transfer,” Cell 153, no. 6 [2013]: 1228–1238, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cell.2013.05.006; Yamada et al., “Human oocytes reprogram adult somatic nuclei of a type 1 diabetic to diploid pluripotent stem cells,” Nature 510, no. 7506 [2014]: 533–536, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nature13287; Young Gie Chung et al., “Human Somatic Cell Nuclear Transfer Using Adult Cells,” Cell Stem Cell 14, no. 6 [2014]: 777–780, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2014.03.015.)
[96] The average number of oocytes retrieved per donor in Mitalipov’s SCNT paper was 12.2. See Figure 5a in Masahito Tachibana et al., “Human Embryonic Stem Cells Derived by Somatic Cell Nuclear Transfer,” Cell 153, no. 6 (2013): 1233, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cell.2013.05.006.
[97] If we assume that an egg market that involves 100,000 retrieval procedures per year would require paying each egg provider at least $10,000 for each retrieval cycle, then the total amount paid to egg providers per year would be at least $1 billion.
[98] Tobias Deuse et al., “SCNT-Derived ESCs with Mismatched Mitochondria Trigger an Immune Response in Allogeneic Hosts,” Cell Stem Cell 16, no. 1 (2015): 33–38, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2014.11.003.
[99] Ibid.
[100] See, for example, Ignacio Sancho-Martinez and J. Izpisua Belmonte, “Will SCNT-ESCs Be Better than iPS cells for Personalized Regenerative Medicine?,” Cell Stem Cell 13, no. 2 (2013): 141–142, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2013.07.013.
[101] Sally Lehrman, “No More Cloning Around,” Scientific American 299 (July 21, 2008): 102, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/scientificamerican0808-100.
[102] Alan Trounson and Natalie D. DeWitt, “Pluripotent Stem Cells from Cloned Human Embryos: Success at Long Last,” Cell Stem Cell 12, no. 6, (2013): 636–638, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2013.05.022.
[103] Jose B. Cibelli, “Human Somatic Cell Nuclear Transfer Is Alive and Well,” Cell Stem Cell 14, no. 6, (2014): 699–701, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2014.05.013.
[104] Ignacio Sancho-Martinez and J. Izpisua Belmonte, “Will SCNT-ESCs Be Better than iPS cells for Personalized Regenerative Medicine?” Cell Stem Cell 13, no. 2 (2013): 142, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2013.07.013.
[105] Ibid.
[106] Insoo Hyun, “Moving human SCNT research forward ethically,” Cell Stem Cell 9, no. 4 (2011): 296, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stem.2011.08.001.
[107] Momoko Maekawa et al., “Direct reprogramming of somatic cells is promoted by maternal transcription factor Glis1,” Nature 474, no. 7350 (2011): 225–229, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nature10106.
[108] Ibid.
[109] Ethics Advisory Board, Department of Health, Education, and Welfare (HEW), “HEW Support of Research Involving Human In Vitro Fertilization and Embryo Transfer,” Fed. Reg. 44 (June 18, 1979): 101, https://repository.library.georgetown.edu/bitstream/handle/10822/559350/HEW_IVF_report.pdf.
[110] United Kingdom Department of Health & Social Security, Report of the Committee of Inquiry Into Human Fertilisation and Embryology (London: Her Majesty’s Stationery Office, 1984): 62.
[111] Daniel Callahan, “The Puzzle of Profound Respect,” Hastings Center Report 25, no. 1 (January–February 1995), 39–40, http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/3562493.
[112] D.W. Brock, “Is a consensus possible on stem cell research? Moral and political obstacles,” Journal of Medical Ethics 32, no. 1 (January 2006): 39, http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/jme.2005.013581. However, as Daniel Callahan has noted, “How are we to go about establishing some kind of moral proportionality between the claims of research” and the claim of the embryo’s moral status? Daniel Callahan, “The Puzzle of Profound Respect,” 39.
[113] For an overview of ANT, see William B. Hurlbut, “Altered nuclear transfer as a morally acceptable means for the procurement of human embryonic stem cells,” Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 48, no. 2, (2005): 211–228, http://dx.doi.org/10.1353/pbm.2005.0055. More information can also be found at http://www.alterednucleartransfer.com.
[114] Ibid., 225.
[115] Ibid., 221–222.
[116] Paul Ramsey, The Patient as Person: Explorations in Medical Ethics (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2002) xlviii. (In the original: “physicians must in greater measure become moral philosophers.”)
[117] Douglas A. Melton, George Q. Daley, and Charles G. Jennings, “Altered Nuclear Transfer in Stem-Cell Research — A Flawed Proposal,” New England Journal of Medicine 351 (2004): 2792, http://dx.doi.org/10.1056/NEJMp048348.
[118] Melton et al., 2792.
[119] Maureen L. Condic, “Alternative sources of pluripotent stem cells: altered nuclear transfer,” Cell Proliferation 41 (2008): 7, http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1365-2184.2008.00484.x.
[120] Alexander Meissner and Rudolf Jaenisch, “Generation of nuclear transfer-derived pluripotent ES cells from cloned Cdx2-deficient blastocysts,” Nature 439 (2006): 212, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nature04257.
[121] Ibid.
[122] Ibid., 213.
[123] See, for example, Thomas P. Zwaka, “Stem cells: Troublesome memories,” Nature 467, no. 7313 (2010): 280–281, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/467280a.
[124] According to law professor Lisa C. Ikemoto, “combining human embryonic stem cells with SCNT [cloning] has been a gold standard of stem cell research.” Lisa C. Ikemoto “Can Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research Escape Its Troubled History?,” Hastings Center Review 44, no. 6, (2014): 7, http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/hast.380.
[125] Rudolf Jaenisch, testimony on Recent Scientific and Clinical Developments, President’s Council on Bioethics, July 24, 2003, https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/pcbe/transcripts/july03/session3.html.
[126] In fact, this terminology was suggested in 1984, several years after the first mouse embryonic stem cells were derived. J. Rossant and V.E. Papaioannou, “The relationship between embryonic, embryonal carcinoma and embryo-derived stem cells,” Cell Differentiation 15, no. 2 (1984): 155–161, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/0045-6039(84)90068-X.
[127] Thomas P. Zwaka and James A. Thomson, “A germ cell origin of embryonic stem cells?,” Development 132, no. 2 (January 2005), 228, http://dx.doi.org/10.1242/dev.01586.
[128] Ibid.; Mia Buehr and Austin Smith, “Genesis of embryonic stem cells,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B 358, no. 1436 (2003): 1397–1402, http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2003.1327; Janet Rossant, “Stem Cells from the Mammalian Blastocyst,” Stem Cells 19, no. 6 (2001): 477–482, http://dx.doi.org/10.1634/stemcells.19-6-477.
[129] Thomas P. Zwaka and James A. Thomson, “A germ cell origin of embryonic stem cells?,” 228.
[130] Felicia W. Pagliuca et al., “Generation of Functional Human Pancreatic ß Cells In Vitro,” Cell 159, no. 2 (2014): 428–439, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.cell.2014.09.040.
[131] Sara Reardon and David Cyranoski, “Japan stem-cell trial stirs envy,” Nature 513, no. 7518 (2014): 287–288, http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/513287a.
[132] Hiroyuki Kamao et al., “Characterization of Human Induced Pluripotent Stem Cell-Derived Retinal Pigment Epithelium Cell Sheets Aiming for Clinical Application,” Stem Cell Reports 2, no. 2 (2014): 205–218, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.stemcr.2013.12.007; Hoshimi Kanemura et al., “Tumorigenicity Studies of Induced Pluripotent Stem Cell (iPSC)-Derived Retinal Pigment Epithelium (RPE) for the Treatment of Age-Related Macular Degeneration,” PLoS One 9, no. 1 (2014), http://dx.doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0085336.
[133] Ron Reagan, speech at the Democratic National Convention, op. cit.
The Witherspoon Council on Ethics and the Integrity of Science, “Part Three: The Case Against Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research,” The New Atlantis, Number 46, Summer 2015, pp. 51-73.

Exhausted by “science says”?

During Covid, The New Atlantis has offered an independent alternative. In this unsettled moment, we need your help to continue.